Economics / Critical Essay

Vol. 4, NO. 4 / July 2019

General equilibrium theory, or GET, is the metatheory on which all of mainstream economics rests; it remains very abstract, and it has been carefully studied by only a small number of economists. Invented by the French economist Léon Walras in 1899, GET was neglected for half a century as economists dealt with the intensifying business cycle, the emergence of central banks, and the Great Depression. The economists who began to take notice of it in the 1950s tended to be applied mathematicians, or, at least, economists with strongly analytical gifts.1 In the 1960s, a debate arose between John Maynard Keynes’s students at Cambridge University and mathematical economists at MIT. Known as the Cambridge capital controversy, the debate called into question the presumption that aggregation functions defined over microeconomic models could coherently yield a macroeconomic model of the economy.2

Controversy and critique led economists to microfounded models in which micro and macroeconomic theories were, at least, presumptively consistent. The standard microfounded economic model, used by many central banks and presented to graduate students, is the dynamic stochastic general equilibrium model.3 It is available in two forms or flavors: the New Classical and the New Keynesian. Both sides see the economy tending toward a perfectly efficient outcome. They disagree only on how difficult it is to get there. New Classicals think it easy. They see economic laws operating in a vacuum, with little or no resistance from nonmarket actors. New Keynesians think it difficult. They see unavoidable rigidities in the real world—wages that do not fall fast enough—or factors internal to the market itself, such as the cost of changing price lists when prices change. For this reason, the New Keynesians often appeal to what they term short and long periods, times in which the economy’s general equilibrium is off and times in which it is on.

For all that, there is little disagreement about the general framework. Neither side doubts that markets move toward general equilibrium, if only because all neoclassical models assume that they do. The point is still more general: any model that invokes a market-clearing mechanism is committed to some sort of general equilibrium—an equilibrium in all markets simultaneously. This commitment is a matter of faith, and if ever questions are raised about GET, they remain within GET.4 Joan Robinson once said of economic models that they must abstract from the real economy. A map on a one-to-one scale is useless. She was right of course, but a map that does not accurately reflect the terrain is useless, no matter the scale. If the GET really does underpin the models that economists use to examine market economies, then surely we must be interested in how closely these models match the real world.

Groping and Auctions

In Éléments d’économie politique pure (Elements of Pure Economics), Walras introduced economists to the notion of tâtonnement:

What must we do in order to prove that the theoretical solution is identically [emphasis added] the solution worked out by the market? Our task is very simple: we need only show that the upward and downward movement of prices solve the system of equations of offer and demand by the process of groping [‘par tâtonnement’].5

Two words stand out in this paragraph: “identically” and “simple.” Walras is not shy about making large claims for the theory that he is expounding: the theoretical solution to his system of equations is “identically the solution worked out by the market.” Did Walras have any proof of this? Not obviously. All we are told is that the “task is very simple.”

On the contrary, the task is not simple at all.

Within the literature of GET, background assumptions are sometimes encompassed by the figure of the Walrasian auctioneer.6 Imagine that all economic transactions take place at auction. The participants are highly numerate agents whose preferences are transparent and assigned exact prices. A is willing to pay $1 for a banana, but not one cent more; B, $275 million for a superyacht, but not one dollar more. The auctioneer collects the offers for all products at all their potential prices. These serve as inputs to Walras’s system of equations. G. L. S. Shackle sets out the underlying assumptions:

Equilibrium is … a means by which all persons in choosing their acts can be supposed to have equal and perfect relevant knowledge and equal freedom. Given a list of persons, besides himself, composing the society, and given for each of these persons a list of all the acts possible to that person, each person can be supposed to draw up a list of all the distinct combinations of acts, one or other of which combinations will constitute the circumstances surrounding his own act. For each of these combinations he can be supposed to specify the act that he himself would choose, in case he were assured that the combination in question would prevail. The conditional promises, one for each person, thus derived, can now be supposed to be treated as a system to be simultaneously solved.7

That system of equations solved, the result is a general equilibrium at which the market is settled.

So much for the high-level view; but in the real world, one might think, an auction such as this would be asking a lot. Given an auctioneer recording prices, every market participant would be required to perform an enormous number of calculations and, what is more, generally without access to the thoughts of others. Walras’s auctioneer is obviously an imaginary figure, an aide to thought.8

This Walras knew.

If general equilibrium is not reached by means of a simultaneous comparison of prices, plans, and intentions, convergence to general equilibrium happens anyway, Walras argued, through trial and error, a kind of controlled groping.

Thus, tâtonnement.

It is a word that has beguiled generations of economists. But it is curious that they have, those generations, left an important question unasked: how likely is it that tâtonnement could force an economy to converge to a point of general equilibrium?

The Test Case

It is almost always profitable to study questions about probabilities by considering something like a test case in which probabilities are perfectly random. If, in the real world, processes seem to depart from randomness, a test case allows the statistician to ask by what extent; and it allows the economist, much occupied by claims of tâtonnement—economic agents in a mutual grope—to ask whether all that groping might, by itself, explain a departure from randomness.

The test case admits of computation. It is possible to consider the number of transactions taking place in a market economy and then calculate the odds that a general equilibrium might be reached by chance. Under such a scheme, agents are undertaking various transactions randomly. They have no information relative to other agents, and the auctioneer posts no prices. Trial and error is useless. There are no trials, and hence no errors. The most comprehensive data that can be amassed are for the economy of the United States. The number of transactions per adult per month, together with the total number of adults, is laid out in Table 1.9

Table 1.

Year Adult population Monthly transactions per adult
2000 223,468,159 46
2003 231,239,350 47
2006 239,661,291 52
2009 247,407,419 55
2012 254,333,400 57
2015 261,447,213 61
2016 263,745,653 62

If we assume absolutely no information on the part of various agents, we are faced with a combinatorial problem known as hats-in-a-ring. A number of men check their hats into a cloakroom. The cloakroom assistant is not paying attention and mixes them up. When the men come to collect their hats, the assistant gives hats back to the men at random. If a given agent is acting with zero information about the decisions of other agents, his transactions will be undertaken blindly, in the same way as the cloakroom assistant picks hats blindly and hands them back to the men.10 The solution to this problem is

Pr n matches hatk|Ek=1e*n!k,

where n is the number of agents, k is the number of hats or transactions, and e is the base of the natural logarithm. Results are presented in Table 2, along with a calculation of the probability of reaching an equilibrium if trials had been undertaken every month since the onset of the Big Bang—approximately 165,588,000,000 months.11

Table 2.

Year Probability of chance equilibrium Probability of chance equilibrium occurring if attempted every month since the Big Bang
2000 10–81361711897 10–81361711885
2003 10–86182688876 10–86182688864
2006 10–99017447269 10–99017447257
2009 10–108303000000 10–108302999988
2012 10–115557196520 10–115557196508
2015 10–127316547417 10–127316547405
2016 10–130603480007 10–130603479995

These numbers are uninspiring.12 Finding a general equilibrium by chance is effectively impossible. I must not be misunderstood. The existence of a general equilibrium is not in doubt. A number of sophisticated mathematical economists have demonstrated this. But as much is true in the theory of ordinary differential equations, where any number of theorems guarantee that existence and uniqueness of solutions to various initial value problems. Finding the solution is another problem. And so is the problem of finding a point of general equilibrium. Whatever the answer, it cannot be by chance. These sorts of probabilities are in the region of miracles, not of science.

A Walk Back from Randomness

If general equilibrium is not reached randomly, just how is it reached? The auctioneer may be allowed to depart. If tâtonnement is left, it is no easy business to see how it prevails. No one would argue that economic agents have no information about the intentions and desires of other market actors. Yet every agent has extremely limited information.13 What does groping look like in a fixed-price retail outlet or in a situation that does not allow for haggling? These problems solved, what does it mean that the number of transactions seems to be increasing at a faster rate than the number of agents needed to process information?

That extra computing power—where is it coming from?

These questions are, if provocative, also vague. Still, Walras claimed that it was simple to transfer the model to a market economy. At the very least, in light of these calculations, that claim needs much more argument than anyone has provided. Equilibrium theories are broadly conceived in terms of long periods. In economic policy discussions, most of the debate centers on how far off this long period actually is. If this long period does, indeed, exist, and if an economist can demonstrate the probity of GET, this might open up a sensible empirical discussion of how far off it is. In this regard, consider these remarks, taken from an extremely popular textbook:

[M]arkets are usually a good way to organize economic activity… In any economic system, scarce resources have to be allocated among competing uses. Market economies harness the forces of supply and demand to serve that end. Supply and demand together determine the prices of the economy’s many different goods and services; prices in turn are the signals that guide the allocation of resources.14

This statement might well be true. But it is not currently supported by economic theory. If GET cannot be shown to be an accurate reflection of existing market economies, then economics does not possess any theory that tells us that market forces automatically produce optimal outcomes, no matter how often mathematical economists demonstrate that optimal outcomes exist. If not really true, then perhaps the above statement is true in the more limited sense that alternative economic arrangements were put in place in the twentieth century that did not work well. This judgment rests on historical induction. Perhaps it will work better tomorrow.

What the facts suggest is that when agents are faced with relative pricing in a market economy, they are overloaded with information. Just possibly, we may not know how relative prices are set. That said, how do we ourselves behave when faced with an informational overload? Trying to price a good, I would emulate current market prices. That would be easy if the product I were selling was already available on the market. Introducing a novel good, I would try to find a similar item and base my price on it. Could such a process be modeled? It is not easy to see how. But it seems intuitively much closer to the truth than any appeals to imaginary auctions, auctioneers, or some barely coherent process of groping.

Scraping By

Economists trusting in the existence of GET have vested their confidence in a point that cannot be reached by chance; they have provided very little guidance on how it might be reached in any other way. Does this mean we just have to scrap economic theory? No. It does mean that economics would be a far more successful discipline if it studied aggregate behaviors that are easily observable in the wide range of economic statistics that we possess. Some economists have pointed in this direction, making reference to the latest talk in other disciplines about emergent properties.15 This buzzword signals a shifting in the sciences away from the methodological approaches of the atomists, who build up their picture of reality piece by piece, and toward a more Aristotelian approach, beginning from the basic principle that the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. A chaque jour suffit sa peine. This essay is meant only as a challenge to general equilibrium theory. To those championing the theory, a request: make a case for the departure from randomness that is intuitively plausible. Once done, if it can be done at all, discussion about many policy issues will become more sophisticated.

Until then, GET should be seen for what it is.16

Endmark

  1. Indeed, many of the founders of modern general equilibrium theory were quite aware that it was far too abstract to be used as a basis for economic analysis and said so explicitly. 
  2. Avi Cohen and Geoff Harcourt, “Whatever Happened to the Cambridge Capital Controversies?,” Journal of Economic Perspectives 17, no. 1 (2003): 199–214. 
  3. The extent to which the neoclassical models before the 1970s rested on general equilibrium is an interesting one. It seems to the present writer that they must have implicitly rested on general equilibrium principles because they assumed that all markets “cleared.” It seems hard to disentangle from general equilibrium the notion that all markets should clear. It is probably fair to say that the pre-1970s neoclassical models implicitly rested on general equilibrium and those that were worked on after the critiques explicitly did. 
  4. However, in the mid-1970s, Hugo Sonnenschein, Rolf Mantel, and Gérard Debreu published a theorem that proved that the general equilibrium framework could not be used to infer a unique equilibrium due to the existence of an excess demand function. Leading general equilibrium theorist Frank Hahn wrote that this could be construed as overturning microfoundations in economics. Frank Hahn, “Revival of Political Economy: The Wrong Issues and the Wrong Argument,” The Economic Record 51, no. 135 (1975): 360–64.

    It is an enduring mystery why this has not received widespread attention among economists. For posterity’s sake, it should be noted that G. L. S. Shackle actually described this flaw in the theory some years before. Philip Pilkington, The Reformation in Economics: A Deconstruction and Reconstruction of Economic Theory (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016), 87–90. 
  5. Léon Walras, Elements of Pure Economics: Or, The Theory of Social Wealth, trans. William Jaffé (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1926), 170. 
  6. Some recent translators have complained about what they consider to be a misrepresentation of Walras’s intention in this story. They claim that the original translator, William Jaffé, wrongly used the word “auctioneer” where Walras intended a crier. Auctions are centrally planned events, and auctioneers are effectively central planners. The sorts of criers found in old stock markets, however, ensured that all prices were “openly announced and an opportunity [was] given to sellers to lower their prices and to buyers to raise their bids” (Léon Walras, Elements of Pure Economics: Or, The Theory of Social Wealth, trans. William Jaffé (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1926), 84). These translators say that this slip by Jaffé was a momentous error that has misled generations of readers into thinking that the market in Walras’s model is an auction market and that he assigned the function of changing prices in his model to an auctioneer (Léon Walras, Elements of Theoretical Economics: Or, The Theory of Social Wealth, trans. Donald Walker and Jan van Daal (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014), xxxv).

    But what difference does it really make? We are dealing with an analogy, a thought experiment. Walras, his translators, and all the rest of us know that market economies are not run through a centralized auction. Likewise, we know that market economies are not run through centralized stock exchanges with prices on all goods being set by criers and countercriers. Which is a neater metaphor? Readers can decide for themselves, probably based on their personal levels of exposure to auctions or stock markets. But this is beside the point. The key question is the extent to which these analogies can be said to hold when transferred off the pages of Walras’s book into actually existing market economies. 
  7. George Shackle, A Scheme of Economic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965), 12–13. Shackle’s entire chapter illuminates the general equilibrium problem. 
  8. To update the Walrasian metaphor, what is assumed is the equivalent of a Borg collective as it functions in the Star Trek science fiction universe. The Borg are half-humanoid, half-robotic creatures who are connected through a giant network. They operate in unison at all times and make decisions in a decentralized manner through instantaneous telepathic communication with one another. In order to do this, every thought of every Borg at any given moment must also be present to every other Borg. This is actually a similar setup to the Walrasian equilibrium theory. The Borg are thought to be hyperefficient due to their ability to communicate instantaneously and make decisions in unison, much like the market is thought to be in the Walrasian system. What they gain in efficiency, however, they lose in freedom and privacy; this makes them repulsive and a threat to other species in the universe. Perhaps, at the level of moral judgment, the same could be said of the Walrasian system. Yet it is often bandied around as a theory of a free-market system. To which we might reply: if all action is predetermined, what freedom? 
  9. The data are not readily available. The Federal Reserve Payments Study provides information on noncash payments. In order to get total payments, we had to source payment diaries that central banks ask consumers to keep in order to track the share of cash to noncash payments. Using this information, we can then estimate the total number of transactions—cash and noncash—in the economy in any given year. Sourcing these payment diaries was difficult, and in addition to those provided by the Federal Reserve of Atlanta, we also had to proxy some years from the Bank of Canada, under the assumption that the composition of payments undertaken by Americans and Canadians is not too dissimilar. Federal Reserve, Federal Reserve Payments Study (2017). Federal Reserve Bank of Atlanta, Diary of Consumer Payment Choice (2016). Ben Fung, Miguel Molico, and Gerald Stuber, “Electronic Money and Payments: Recent Developments and Issues,” Bank of Canada Discussion Paper (2014). 
  10. Some might protest that the two cases are not analogous because in an economy some transactions will be for the same goods. So, say, 1% of all transactions will be for bread. Thus, unlike the hat and cloakroom example, some transactions will not be unique. But this is not the point. Even if 1% of transactions are for bread, each of these transactions will be unique in that they will represent a totally unique willingness to pay for this bread. You may be willing to spend up to $1 on a loaf; I may be willing to spend up to $1.50. Both of these transactions are thus unique. 
  11. This sort of blow up has come to be known as combinatorial inflation. 
  12. I am infinitely indebted to William Briggs for assistance with these calculations and with casting the statistical framework in which to think through this problem. Any flaw in the use of the analogy, however, is solely my fault. 
  13. And this is to leave aside the question of decisions that must be made with reference to an uncertain future. For example, savings decisions are made in an environment where the saver cannot know what the consumption basket will look like in, say, 10 years when he intends on spending his savings. This is not a question of probabilistic risk. I cannot put probabilities on the existence or price of, say, a flying car 10 years hence. Here we are in the domain of uncertainty proper, as so aptly highlighted first by John Maynard Keynes. John Maynard Keynes, “The State of Long-Term Expectation,” in The General Theory of Employment, Money and Interest (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1936), 129–44. 
  14. Gregory Mankiw, Principles of Economics (Mason, OH: South-Western Cengage Learning, 2011), 84. 
  15. John King, The Microfoundations Delusion: Metaphor and Dogma in the History of Macroeconomics (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2012). 
  16. The opinions expressed in this essay are those of the author and do not reflect those of his employer. 

Philip Pilkington is a Research Analyst at the investment management firm GMO and author of the blog Fixing the Economists.


More from this Contributor

More on Economics


Endmark

Copyright © Inference 2024

ISSN #2576–4403